A
Note on Dialectic
by Herbert Marcuse (1960)
(Supplemental
preface to Reason & Revolution: Hegel and the Rise of Social
Theory)
This book [Reason & Revolution] was written in the
hope that it would make a small contribution to the revival, not of
Hegel, but of a mental faculty which is in danger of being obliterated:
the power of negative thinking. As Hegel defines it: “Thinking is,
indeed, essentially the negation of that which is immediately before
us.” What does he mean by “negation,” the central category of the
dialectic?
Even Hegel’s
most abstract and metaphysical concepts are saturated with experience—experience
of a world in which the unreasonable becomes reasonable and, as such,
determines the facts; in which unfreedom is the condition of freedom,
and war the guarantor of peace. This world contradicts itself. Common
sense and science purge themselves from this contradiction; but philosophical
thought begins with the recognition that the facts do not correspond
to the concepts imposed by common sense and scientific reason—in short,
with the refusal to accept them. To the extent that these concepts
disregard the fatal contradictions which make up reality, they abstract
from the very process of reality. The negation which the dialectic
applies to them is not only a critique of conformist logic, which
denies the reality of contradictions; it is also a critique of the
given state of affairs on its own ground—of the established system
of life, which denies its of promises and potentialities.
Today,
this dialectical mode of thought is alien to the whole established
universe of discourse and action. It seems to belong to the past and
to be rebutted by the achievements of technological civilization.
The established reality seems promising and productive enough to repel
or absorb all alternatives. Thus acceptance—and even affirmation—of
this reality appears to be the only reasonable methodological principle.
Moreover, it precludes neither criticism nor change; on the contrary,
insistence on the dynamic character of the status quo, on its constant
“revolutions,” is one of the strongest props for this attitude. Yet
this dynamic seems to operate endlessly within the same framework
of life: streamlining rather than abolishing the domination of man,
both by man and by the products of his labor. Progress becomes quantitative
and tends to delay indefinitely the turn from quantity to quality—that
is, the emergence of new modes of existence with new forms of reason
and freedom.
The power
of negative thinking is the driving power of dialectical thought,
used as a tool for analyzing the world of facts in terms of its internal
inadequacy. I choose this vague and unscientific formulation in order
to sharpen the contrast between dialectical and undialectical thinking.
“Inadequacy” implies a value judgement. Dialectical thought invalidates
the a priori opposition of value and fact by understanding all facts
as stages of a single process—a process in which subject and object
are so joined that truth can be determined only within the subject-object
totality. All facts embody the knower as well as the doer; they continuously
translate the past into the present. The objects thus “contain” subjectivity
in their very structure.
Now what
(or who) is this subjectivity that, in a literal sense, constitutes
the objective world? Hegel answers with a series of terms denoting
the subject in its various manifestations: Thought, Reason, Spirit,
Idea. Since we no longer have that fluent access to these concepts
which the eighteenth and nineteenth century still had, I shall try
to sketch Hegel’s conception in more familiar terms.
Nothing
is “real” which does not sustain itself in existence, in a life-and-death
struggle with the situations and conditions of its existence. The
struggle may be blind or even unconscious, as in inorganic matter;
it may be conscious and concerted, such as the struggle of mankind
with its own conditions and with those of nature. Reality is the constantly
renewed result of the process of existence—the process, conscious
or unconscious in which “that which is” becomes “other than itself”;
and identity is only the continuous negation of inadequate existence,
the subject maintaining itself in being other than itself. Each reality,
therefore, is a realization—a development of “subjectivity.” The latter
“comes to itself” in history, there the development has a rational
content; Hegel defines it as “progress in the consciousness of freedom.”
Again a
value judgement—and this time a value judgement imposed upon the world
as a whole. But freedom is for Hegel an ontological category: it means
being not a mere object, but the subject of one’s existence, not succumbing
to external conditions, but transforming factuality into realization.
This transformation is, according to Hegel, the energy of nature and
history, the inner structure of all being! One may be tempted to scoff
oat this idea, but one should be aware of its implications.
Dialectical
thought starts with the experience that the world is unfree; that
is to say, man and nature exist in conditions of alienation, exist
as “other than they are.” Any mode of thought which excludes this
contradiction from its logic is a faulty logic. Thought “corresponds”
to reality only as it transforms reality by comprehending its contradictory
structure. Here the principle of dialectic drives thought beyond the
limits of philosophy. For to comprehend reality means to comprehend
what things really are, and this in turn means rejecting their mere
factuality. Rejection is the process of thought as well as action.
While the scientific method leads from the immediate experience of
things to their mathematical-logical structure, philosophical thought
leads from the immediate experience of existence to its historical
structure: the principle of freedom.
Freedom
is the innermost dynamic of existence, and the very process of existence
in an unfree world is “the continuous negation of that which threatens
to deny (aufheben) freedom.” Thus freedom is essentially negative;
existence is both alienation and the process by which the subject
comes to itself in comprehending and mastering alienation. For the
history of mankind, this means attainment of a “state of the world”
in which the individual persists in inseparable harmony with the whole,
and in which the conditions and relation of his world “possess no
essential objectivity independent of the individual.” As to the prospect
of attaining such a state, Hegel was pessimistic: the element of reconciliation
with the established state of affairs, so strong in his work, seems
to a great extent due to this pessimism—or, if one prefers, this realism.
Freedom is relegated to the realm of pure thought, to the Absolute
Idea. Idealism by default: Hegel shares this fate with the main philosophical
tradition.
Dialectical
thought thus becomes negative in itself. Its function is to break
down the self-assurance and self-contentment of common sense, to undermine
the sinister confidence in the power and language of facts, to demonstrate
that unfreedom is so much at the core of things that the development
of their internal contradictions leads necessarily to qualitative
change: the explosion and catastrophe of the established state of
affairs. Hegel sees the task of knowledge as that of recognizing the
world as Reason by understanding all objects of thought as elements
and aspects of a totality which becomes a conscious world in the history
of mankind. Dialectical analysis tends to become historical analysis,
in which nature itself appears as part and stage in its own history
and in the history of man. The progress of cognition from common sense
to knowledge arrives at a world which is negative in its very structure
because that which is real opposes and denies the potentialities inherent
in itself—potentialities which themselves strive for realization.
Reason is the negation of the negative.
Interpretation
of that-which-is in terms of that-which-is-not, confrontation of the
given facts with that which they exclude—this has been the concern
of philosophy wherever philosophy was more than a matter of ideological
justification or mental exercise. The liberating function of negation
in philosophical thought depends upon the recognition that the negation
is a positive act: that-which-is repels that-which-is-not and, in
doing so, repels its own real possibilities. Consequently, to express
and define that-which-is on its own terms is to distort and falsify
reality. Reality is other and more than that codified in the logic
and language of facts. Here is the inner link between dialectical
thought and the effort of avant-garde literature: the effort to break
the power of facts over the word, and to speak a language which is
not the language of those who establish, enforce, and benefit from
the facts. As the power of the given facts tends to become totalitarian,
to absorb all opposition, and to define the entire universe of discourse,
the effort to speak the language of contradiction appears increasingly
irrational, obscure, artificial. The question is not that of a direct
or indirect influence of Hegel on the genuine avant-garde, though
it is evident in Mallarmé and Villiers de l’Isle-Adam, in surrealism,
in Brecht. Dialectic and poetic language meet, rather, on common ground.
The common
element is the search for an “authentic language”—the language of
negation as the Great Refusal to accept the rules of a game in which
the dice are loaded. The absent must be made present because the greater
part of truth is in that which is absent. This is Mallarmé’s
classical statement:
Je dis:
une fleur! et, hors de l’oubli où ma voix relége aucun
contour, en tant que quelque chose d’autre que les calices sus, musicalement
se lève, idée même et suave, l’absente de tous
bouquets.
[I say:
a flower! and, out of the oblivion where my voice banishes all contours,
musically rises, different from every known blossom, the one absent
from all bouquets—Idea itself and delicate.]
In the
authentic language, the word
n’est
pas l’expression d’une chose, mais l’absence de cette chose… Le mot
fait disparaître les choses et nous impose le sentiment d’une
manque universel et même de son propre manque.(1)
[is not
the expression of a thing, but rather the absence of this thing… The
word makes the things disappear and imposes upon us the feeling of
a universal want and even of its own want.]
Poetry
is thus the power “denier les choses” (to deny the things)—the
power which Hegel claims, paradoxically, for all authentic thought.
Valéry asserts:
La pensée
est, en somme, le travail qui fait vivre en nous ce qui n’existe pas.(2)
[In short,
thought is the labor which brings to life in us that which does not
exist.]
He asks
the rhetorical question: “que sommes-nous donc sals le secours
de ce qui n’existe pas?(3) (What are we without the help of that
which does not exist?)
This is
not “existentialism.” It is something more vital and more desperate:
the effort to contradict a reality in which all logic and all speech
are false to the extent that they are part of a mutilated whole. The
vocabulary and grammar of the language of contradiction are still
those of the game (there are no others), but the concepts codified
in the language of the game are redefined by relating them to their
“determinate negation.” This term, which denotes the governing principle
of dialectical thought, can be explained only in a textual interpretation
of Hegel’s Logic Here it must suffice to emphasize that, by virtue
of this principle, the dialectical contradiction is distinguished
from all pseudo- and crackpot opposition, beatnik and hipsterism.
The negation is determinate if it refers the established state of
affairs to the basic factors and forces which make for its destructiveness,
as well as for the possible alternatives beyond the status quo. In
the human reality, they are historical factors and forces, and the
determinate negation is ultimately a political negation. As such,
it may well find authentic expression in nonpolitical language, and
the more so as the entire dimension of politics becomes an integral
part of the status quo.
Dialectical
logic is critical logic: it reveals modes and contents of thought
which transcend the codified patterns of use and validation. Dialectical
thought does not invent these contents; they have accrued to the notions
in the long tradition of thought and action. Dialectical analysis
merely assembles and reactivates them; it recovers tabooed meanings
and thus appears almost as a return, or rather a conscious liberation
of the repressed! Since the established universe of discourse is that
of an unfree world, dialectical thought is necessarily destructive,
and whatever liberation it may bring is a liberation in thought, in
theory. However, the divorce of thought from action, of theory from
practice, is itself part of the unfree world. No thought and no theory
can undo it; but theory may help to prepare the ground for their possible
reunion, and the ability of the thought to develop a logic and language
is a prerequisite for this task.
In what,
then, lies the power of negative thinking? Dialectical thought has
not hindered Hegel from developing his philosophy into a neat and
comprehensive system which, in the end, accentuates the positive emphatically.
I believe it is the idea of Reason itself which is the undialectical
element in Hegel’s philosophy. The idea of Reason comprehends everything
and ultimately absolves everything, because it has its place and function
in the whole, and the whole is beyond good and evil, truth and falsehood.
It may even be justifiable, logically as well as historically, to
define Reason in terms which include slavery, the Inquisition, child
labor, concentration camps, gas chambers, and nuclear preparedness.
These may well have been integral parts of that rationality which
has governed the recorded history of mankind. If so, the idea of Reason
itself is at stake; it reveals itself as a part rather than as the
whole. This does not mean that reason abdicates its claim to confront
reality with the truth about reality. On the contrary, when Marxian
theory takes shape as a critique of Hegel’s philosophy, it does so
in the name of Reason. It is consonant with the innermost effort of
Hegel’s thought if his own philosophy is “cancelled,” not by substituting
for Reason some extrarational standards, but by driving Reason itself
to recognize the extent to which it is still unreasonable, blind,
the victim of unmastered forces. Reason, as the developing and applied
knowledge of man—as “free thought”—was instrumental in creating the
world we live in. It was also instrumental in sustaining, toil, and
suffering. But Reason, and Reason alone, contains its own corrective.
In the
Logic, which forms the first part of his System of philosophy, Hegel
anticipates almost literally Wagner’s Parsifal message “the hand that
inflicts the wound is also the hand that heals it.”(4) The context
is the biblical story of the Fall of Man. Knowledge may have caused
the wound in the existence of man, the crime and the guilt; but the
second innocence, the “second harmony,” can be gained only from knowledge.
Redemption can never be the work of a “guileless fool.” Against the
various obscurantists who insist on the right of the irrational versus
the intellect, Hegel inseparably links progress in freedom to progress
in thought, action to theory. Since he accepted the specific historical
form of Reason reached at his time as the reality of Reason the advance
beyond this form of Reason must be an advance of Reason itself; and
since the adjustment of Reason to oppressive social institutions perpetuated
unfreedom, progress in freedom depends on thought becoming political,
in the shape of a theory which demonstrates negation as a political
alternative implicit in the historical situation. Marx’s materialistic
“subversion” of Hegel, therefore, was not a shift from one philosophical
position to another, nor from philosophy to social theory, but rather
a recognition that the established forms of life were reaching the
stage of their historical negation.
This historical
stage has changed the situation of philosophy and of all cognitive
thought. From this stage on, all thinking that does not testify to
an awareness of the radical falsity of the established forms of life
is faulty thinking. Abstraction from this all-pervasive condition
is not merely immoral; it is false. For reality has become technological
reality, and the subject is now joined with the object so closely
that the notion of object necessarily includes the subject. Abstraction
from their interrelation no longer leads to a more genuine reality
but to deception, because even in this sphere the subject itself is
apparently a constitutive part of the object as scientifically determined.
The observing, measuring, calculating subject of scientific method,
and the subject of the daily business of life—both are expressions
of the same subjectivity: man. One did not have to wait for Hiroshima
in order to have one’s eyes opened to this identity. And as always
before, the subject that has conquered matter suffers under the dead
weight of his conquest. Those who enforce and direct this conquest
have used it to create a world in which the increasing comforts of
life and the ubiquitous power of the productive apparatus keep man
enslaved to the prevailing state of affairs. Those social groups which
dialectical theory identified as the forces of negation are either
defeated or reconciled with the established system. Before the power
of the given facts, the power of negative thinking stands condemned.
This power
of facts is an oppressive power; it is the power of man over man,
appearing as objective and rational condition. Against this appearance,
thought continues to protest in the name of truth. And in the name
of fact: for it is the supreme and universal fact that the status
quo perpetuates itself through the constant threat of atomic destruction,
through the unprecedented waste of resources, through mental impoverishment,
and—last but not least—through brute force. These are the unresolved
contradictions. They define every single fact and every single event;
they permeate the entire universe of discourse and action. Thus they
define also the logic of things: that is, the mode of thought capable
of piercing the ideology and of comprehending reality whole. No method
can claim a monopoly of cognition, but no method seems authentic which
does not recognize that these two propositions are meaningful descriptions
of our situation: “The whole is the truth,” and the whole is false.
Notes
1. Maurice Blanchot, “Le Paradoxe d’Aytre,” Les Temps Modernes (June,
1946), p. 1580ff.
2. Ouevres, Bibliothèque de la Pleiade, vol. I, p. 1333.
3. Ibid., p. 966.
4. The Logic of Hegel trans. W. Wallace (Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1895), p. 55.